Cofinal set is uncountable

Consider sequences of natural numbers. We say that a sequence $a$ majorizes $b$, notation $a\succ b$, if $$\lim_{n\to \infty}\frac{b_n}{a_n}=0.$$
We call a set of sequences $C$ cofinal if for any sequence $v$ there is $u\in C$ such that $u$ majorizes $v$.


$\textbf{Statement}.$ Every cofinal set is uncountable.

$\textbf{Proof}.$ The proof is utilization of Cantor's diagonal argument.
Assume $C$ is a cofinal countable set, denote its elements as $a^k$ for $k=1,2,3,\ldots$. First of all observe that $\succ$ is a transitive relation and for any finite set of sequences, there is a sequence $u$ which majorizes all of them (consider $n$ times the pointwise maximum).
Construct a sequence of sequences $b^k$ as follows -
take $b^1_n=\max\{a^1_1,\ldots,a^1_n\}$. Suppose we have constructed $b^j$ for $j=1,\ldots,k$. Construct $b^{k+1}$ as an nondecreasing sequence which majorizes all of $a^i$ for $i=1,\ldots,k+1$ and $b^j$ for $j=1,\ldots,k$.
Thus $b^j\succ a^j$ and $b^{j+1}\succ b^j$ and each $b^j$ is nondecreasing sequence.
Let $n_1$ be such that $\displaystyle \frac{b^1_{j}}{b^{2}_j}<\frac{1}{2}$ for $j\ge n_1$. Now for $i>1$ take $n_i \ge\max\{i, \ n_{i-1}\}$ and such that $\displaystyle \frac{b^i_{j}}{b^{i+1}_j}<\frac{1}{2}$ for $j\ge n_i$ . Now define $c_k=b_{n_k}^k$. Take some $a^j$ ($j$ fixed) and we know $b^j\succ a^j$. Now take $k>j$. We have $$\frac{b^j_{n_k}}{c_k}=\frac{b^j_{n_k}}{b_{n_k}^k}=\frac{b^{k-1}_{n_{k}}}{b_{n_k}^k}\cdot \frac{b^{k-2}_{n_{k}}}{b_{n_{k}}^{k-1}}\cdots \frac{b_{n_k}^{j}}{b_{n_k}^{j+1}}.$$ Since $n_k\ge n_i$ when $k>i$ we have that $$\frac{b^{i+1}_{n_{k}}}{b^i_{n_k}}< \frac{1}{2}$$ for $i\in\{j,\cdots k-1\}$. Thus using the above form we have $$\frac{b^j_{n_k}}{c_k}<\frac{1}{2^{k-j}}$$ Since $b^j$ is noncreasing and $n_k\ge k$ we have $$\frac{b^j_{k}}{c_k}\le \frac{b^j_{n_k}}{c_k}<\frac{1}{2^{k-j}}.$$ This means that $c\succ b^j$ for all $j$. Since $b^j\succ a^j$ we see that $c\succ a_j$ for all $j$ which contradicts the fact that $C$ is cofinal.

Characterization of limit ordinals

An ordinal $\alpha$ is limit ordinal if and only if there exists ordinal $\beta$ such that $\alpha=\omega\beta$.

Proof. $\Leftarrow)$ If $\beta=1$ then $\alpha=\omega$ so it is limit. Assume $\omega\gamma$ is limit for all $\gamma<\beta$. We will prove that $\omega\beta$ is limit.
First assume $\beta$ is limit. Then $\omega\beta=\sup\{\omega\gamma \ \big| \ \gamma<\beta\}$. Let $\theta<\omega\beta$, then $\theta<\omega\gamma'$ for some $\gamma'<\beta$. But $\omega\gamma'$ is limit thus $\theta+1<\omega\gamma'$ so $\theta+1<\omega\beta$ hence $\omega\beta$ is limit.
Now let $\beta=\beta'+1$ for some $\beta'$. Thus $\omega\beta=\omega\beta'+\omega$. If $\theta<\omega\beta=\omega\beta'+\omega=\sup\{\omega\beta'+n\ \big| \ n<\omega\}$ then $\theta<\omega\beta'+n_0$ for some $n_0$. And now $\theta+1<\omega\beta'+n_0+1<\sup\{\omega\beta'+n\ \big| \ n<\omega\}$ hence $\omega\beta$ is limit.
$\Rightarrow)$ Let $\beta=\sup\{\gamma\ \big| \ \omega\gamma\le\alpha\}$. We have that $\omega\beta\le \alpha$. Assume $\omega\beta<\alpha$. Since $\alpha$ is limit we find that $\omega\beta+1<\alpha$ and inductively $\omega\beta+n<\alpha$ for all $n<\omega$. Hence $\omega\beta+\omega\le \alpha$. This means that $\omega(\beta+1)\le \alpha$ which is a contradiction with the definition of $\beta$.

Binomial identity

$$\displaystyle \sum_{k=1}^n(-1)^{n-k}\binom{n}{k}k^j=\begin{cases} n!, & j=n\\
0, & j=1,2,\ldots,n\end{cases}$$
Proof. Consider the number of surjective functions $f:\{1,2,\ldots,j\}\to\{1,2,\ldots,n\}$. If we count them using the inclusion-exclusion principle we get the sum in the problem. On the other hand this number is trivially $n!$ if $j=n$ and $0$ if $j<n$.
Remark 1. For $j>n$ we again find the number of surjections, which has a closed form form some $j$.
Remark 2. Interesting identity which represents the above identities in a unified manner is the following $$\sum_{k=0}^n(-1)^{n-k}\binom{n}{k}(x+k)^n=n!$$ for all $x$ (in $\mathbb{R}$ for example, but any commutative ring suffices).

Property of join

 Let $X$ be path-connected and $Y$ be arbitrary topological space. Then the join $X*Y$ is simply connected.   $\textbf{Proof}.$ We use Van K...